梦见小黑蛇是什么预兆| 医院dr检查是什么| 青核桃皮的功效与作用是什么| 水疱疹什么药最快能治好| 左眼皮跳是什么预兆| dob是什么意思| 心五行属性是什么| 靶子是什么意思| 四个火读什么| 64岁属什么| 喝酒之前吃什么保护胃| 炸鸡翅裹什么粉| 省略号的作用是什么| 执拗是什么意思| 落魄是什么意思| fci是什么意思| 胰腺炎是什么| 新疆人为什么长得像外国人| 鼠的三合生肖是什么| 老年人吃什么营养品好| 肾结石是因什么而起| 黑白双煞是什么意思| 梦见自己出嫁是什么意思| da医学上是什么意思| 什么是门户网站| 蘸什么意思| 胃痛按什么部位可以缓解疼痛| 怀孕牙龈出血是什么原因| 土龙是什么鱼| pdo是什么意思| 不解什么| 智齿旁边的牙齿叫什么| panerai是什么牌子| 头晃动是什么病的前兆| 排骨和什么菜搭配最好| 女人吃黄芪有什么好处| 芈月是秦始皇什么人| 什么树没有叶子| 烫伤起水泡涂什么药膏| 宝宝不爱吃饭是什么原因| 多多益善的意思是什么| 保质期是什么意思| 孩子发烧挂什么科| 黑色记号笔用什么能擦掉| 尿白细胞3十什么意思| 早上起来嘴苦口臭是什么原因| 看手指甲挂什么科室| 麦昆牌子是什么档次| 排骨汤里放什么食材好| 易孕期是什么时候| 尿路感染为什么会尿血| 汶字五行属什么| 无可厚非什么意思| 舍曲林是什么药| 停诊是什么意思| 身上长疣是什么原因| 皮肤瘙痒是什么原因| 头发大把大把的掉是什么原因| 怡字五行属什么的| lee是什么品牌| 香蕉不能和什么一起吃| 焦糖色裤子配什么颜色上衣| 佐匹克隆片是什么药| 掉发挂什么科| 机车是什么意思| 县公安局长什么级别| 结果是什么意思| 身体多病戴什么首饰| 手机为什么没信号| 倒走对身体有什么好处| 面试是什么意思| bug是什么意思网络用语| 同化什么意思| 8月6日什么星座| 见风使舵是什么生肖| 什么烟最便宜| 梦见大狼狗是什么意思| 高考什么时候结束| 热的什么| 党委委员是什么级别| 乙肝三项检查什么| 正能量是什么意思| 什么是多囊| 针眼用什么眼药水| 感冒喝什么药| 菡什么意思| 顺风顺水什么意思| 为什么伤口愈合会痒| 晚上尿多是什么原因| 为什么会有霉菌性阴道炎| 中医是什么| 2月7号什么星座| 厚子鱼是什么鱼| 胃烧心是什么感觉| 瑞典和瑞士有什么区别| 料理机是干什么用的| 海星吃什么食物| 噤口痢是什么意思| 精油有什么作用| 细菌性感冒吃什么药效果好| 心什么诚服| 牛肉可以炖什么| p.a.是什么意思| 什么是骨癌| 痈疽是什么意思| 考试前吃巧克力有什么好处| 什么是泥炭土| ppa是什么药| 梅核气吃什么药| 陕西有什么特产| 反胃是什么原因引起的| 尿蛋白两个加号是什么意思| 早期复极是什么意思| 十岁小孩尿床是什么原因| 垣字五行属什么| 脑花是什么东西| 11月有什么节日| 贡生相当于现在的什么| 干事是什么意思| 姓丁的女孩起什么名字好| 运是什么意思| 梨花是什么颜色| 肝在什么位置图片| 柠檬茶喝了有什么好处| 兔子为什么不吃窝边草| 什么是渎职| 非萎缩性胃炎吃什么药| 生理期是什么意思| 梦到老公被蛇咬是什么意思| 一什么牛奶| 血糖高吃什么主食| 哽咽是什么意思| 澄面是什么面粉| 十玉九裂是什么意思| 吃什么利尿| 煽是什么意思| 九月十号是什么节日| 焦虑是什么意思| 眼睛痒用什么眼药水好| 四个一是什么字| 1978年属马五行缺什么| 爱心是什么牌子| 天秤座属于什么星象| 剑兰什么时候开花| 南京有什么特色特产| 子宫占位是什么意思| cv是什么| 内能与什么因素有关| 海员是干什么的| 石见读什么| 贝伐珠单抗是什么药| 鸡飞狗跳是什么生肖| 梦到头发白了是什么意思| 冷藏和冷冻有什么区别| 肝实质回声不均匀是什么意思| 外冷内热是什么症状| 衣带渐宽终不悔是什么意思| 一直干咳是什么原因| 品牌是什么意思| 梦龙什么口味好吃| 补气血吃什么食物最好| 明年是什么年啊| 例假少吃什么药| 高密度脂蛋白偏高是什么意思| 何妨是什么意思| 梦见手机丢了又找到了是什么意思| 相得益彰意思是什么| 肾上腺素高会导致什么| samsonite什么牌子| 中焦不通吃什么药| 马齿苋长什么样| 里急后重吃什么药最好| 牛肉饺子馅配什么蔬菜| 丙氨酸氨基转移酶高吃什么药| 双侧输尿管不扩张是什么意思| 郴州有什么好玩的景点| 扳机指是什么原因造成的| ada医学上是什么意思| 为什么射不出来| 九什么一毛| 为什么会骨盆前倾| 高血压是什么原因引起的| 儿童中暑吃什么药| 经常想睡觉是什么原因| 清明节在什么时候| 凉粉果什么时候成熟| 手心经常出汗是什么原因| 女性割礼是什么| 为什么腋下会长小肉揪| 什么食物含维生素b| 肝损伤吃什么药| 7月19号是什么星座| 贫血做什么检查能查出来| rf是什么| 血小板升高是什么原因| nba新赛季什么时候开始| 秋天有什么水果成熟| 莫迪是什么种姓| 球蛋白低是什么原因| 肠胃不好适合喝什么茶| 尿酸高吃什么药降尿酸效果好| 为什么早上起来恶心想吐| 美国属于什么洲| 萎缩性胃炎不能吃什么食物| 然五行属性是什么| 紫水晶五行属什么| 985代表什么意思| 84消毒液不能和什么一起用| 孕妇缺铁吃什么| 什么属于发物| 参片泡水喝有什么功效| 鼻窦炎用什么药| 吃豌豆有什么好处| 吃灵芝有什么好处| 拉肚子吃什么药| 人中深浅代表什么| 云南是什么民族| 金戊念什么| 氨基酸什么牌子好| 光动力治疗什么| 二脚趾比大脚趾长代表什么| 乳腺ca是什么意思| 低血压吃什么食物好| 中医减肥挂什么科| 高胆固醇吃什么药| 轻奢是什么意思| 杏色搭配什么颜色好看| 鼠加句念什么| 皇帝菜是什么菜| 什么人每天靠运气赚钱| 月柱代表什么| 笏是什么意思| 煞星是什么意思| 什么是公历| 皮肤发白一块一块的是什么病| 突然的反义词是什么| 珍珠母贝是什么东西| 什么是恒牙| 刻薄什么意思| 什么作用| lg手机是什么牌子| 不经意间是什么意思| 肝不好吃什么中成药| 主动脉硬化吃什么药好| 新疆人为什么不吃猪肉| eric是什么意思| 胱抑素c高是什么原因| 清晰是什么意思| 难免流产什么意思| 打水光针有什么副作用| 杜甫被称为什么| 多汗症是什么原因引起的| 利福平是什么药| 补肾壮阳吃什么好| 心脑血管疾病吃什么药| 双顶径是什么意思| 往返是什么意思| 风心病是什么病| 阴道炎用什么栓剂| 一黑一白是什么蛇| 什么如既往| 取环后需要注意什么| 撰文是什么意思| 浮现是什么意思| 百度Jump to content

吴昕换了个发色气场都不一样了 嫩照玩转巴黎

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 1941年6月3日,陕甘宁边区召开县长联席会议讨论征粮问题。

In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics.

A precursor to second-order arithmetic that involves third-order parameters was introduced by David Hilbert and Paul Bernays in their book Grundlagen der Mathematik.[1] The standard axiomatization of second-order arithmetic is denoted by Z2.

Second-order arithmetic includes, but is significantly stronger than, its first-order counterpart Peano arithmetic. Unlike Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic allows quantification over sets of natural numbers as well as numbers themselves. Because real numbers can be represented as (infinite) sets of natural numbers in well-known ways, and because second-order arithmetic allows quantification over such sets, it is possible to formalize the real numbers in second-order arithmetic. For this reason, second-order arithmetic is sometimes called "analysis".[2]

Second-order arithmetic can also be seen as a weak version of set theory in which every element is either a natural number or a set of natural numbers. Although it is much weaker than Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, second-order arithmetic can prove essentially all of the results of classical mathematics expressible in its language.

A subsystem of second-order arithmetic is a theory in the language of second-order arithmetic each axiom of which is a theorem of full second-order arithmetic (Z2). Such subsystems are essential to reverse mathematics, a research program investigating how much of classical mathematics can be derived in certain weak subsystems of varying strength. Much of core mathematics can be formalized in these weak subsystems, some of which are defined below. Reverse mathematics also clarifies the extent and manner in which classical mathematics is nonconstructive.

Definition

[edit]

Syntax

[edit]

The language of second-order arithmetic is two-sorted. The first sort of terms and in particular variables, usually denoted by lower case letters, consists of individuals, whose intended interpretation is as natural numbers. The other sort of variables, variously called "set variables", "class variables", or even "predicates" are usually denoted by upper-case letters. They refer to classes/predicates/properties of individuals, and so can be thought of as sets of natural numbers. Both individuals and set variables can be quantified universally or existentially. A formula with no bound set variables (that is, no quantifiers over set variables) is called arithmetical. An arithmetical formula may have free set variables and bound individual variables.

Individual terms are formed from the constant 0, the unary function S (the successor function), and the binary operations + and (addition and multiplication). The successor function adds 1 to its input. The relations = (equality) and < (comparison of natural numbers) relate two individuals, whereas the relation ∈ (membership) relates an individual and a set (or class). Thus in notation the language of second-order arithmetic is given by the signature .

For example, , is a well-formed formula of second-order arithmetic that is arithmetical, has one free set variable X and one bound individual variable n (but no bound set variables, as is required of an arithmetical formula)—whereas is a well-formed formula that is not arithmetical, having one bound set variable X and one bound individual variable n.

Semantics

[edit]

Several different interpretations of the quantifiers are possible. If second-order arithmetic is studied using the full semantics of second-order logic then the set quantifiers range over all subsets of the range of the individual variables. If second-order arithmetic is formalized using the semantics of first-order logic (Henkin semantics) then any model includes a domain for the set variables to range over, and this domain may be a proper subset of the full powerset of the domain of individual variables.[3]

Axioms

[edit]

Basic

[edit]

The following axioms are known as the basic axioms, or sometimes the Robinson axioms. The resulting first-order theory, known as Robinson arithmetic, is essentially Peano arithmetic without induction. The domain of discourse for the quantified variables is the natural numbers, collectively denoted by N, and including the distinguished member , called "zero."

The primitive functions are the unary successor function, denoted by prefix , and two binary operations, addition and multiplication, denoted by the infix operator "+" and "", respectively. There is also a primitive binary relation called order, denoted by the infix operator "<".

Axioms governing the successor function and zero:

  1. ("the successor of a natural number is never zero")
  2. ("the successor function is injective")
  3. ("every natural number is zero or a successor")

Addition defined recursively:

Multiplication defined recursively:

Axioms governing the order relation "<":

  1. ("no natural number is smaller than zero")
  2. ("every natural number is zero or bigger than zero")

These axioms are all first-order statements. That is, all variables range over the natural numbers and not sets thereof, a fact even stronger than their being arithmetical. Moreover, there is but one existential quantifier, in Axiom 3. Axioms 1 and 2, together with an axiom schema of induction make up the usual Peano–Dedekind definition of N. Adding to these axioms any sort of axiom schema of induction makes redundant the axioms 3, 10, and 11.

Induction and comprehension schema

[edit]

If φ(n) is a formula of second-order arithmetic with a free individual variable n and possibly other free individual or set variables (written m1,...,mk and X1,...,Xl), the induction axiom for φ is the axiom:

The (full) second-order induction scheme consists of all instances of this axiom, over all second-order formulas.

One particularly important instance of the induction scheme is when φ is the formula "" expressing the fact that n is a member of X (X being a free set variable): in this case, the induction axiom for φ is

This sentence is called the second-order induction axiom.

If φ(n) is a formula with a free variable n and possibly other free variables, but not the variable Z, the comprehension axiom for φ is the formula

This axiom makes it possible to form the set of natural numbers satisfying φ(n). There is a technical restriction that the formula φ may not contain the variable Z, for otherwise the formula would lead to the comprehension axiom

,

which is inconsistent. This convention is assumed in the remainder of this article.

The full system

[edit]

The formal theory of second-order arithmetic (in the language of second-order arithmetic) consists of the basic axioms, the comprehension axiom for every formula φ (arithmetic or otherwise), and the second-order induction axiom. This theory is sometimes called full second-order arithmetic to distinguish it from its subsystems, defined below. Because full second-order semantics imply that every possible set exists, the comprehension axioms may be taken to be part of the deductive system when full second-order semantics is employed.[3]

Models

[edit]

This section describes second-order arithmetic with first-order semantics. Thus a model of the language of second-order arithmetic consists of a set M (which forms the range of individual variables) together with a constant 0 (an element of M), a function S from M to M, two binary operations + and · on M, a binary relation < on M, and a collection D of subsets of M, which is the range of the set variables. Omitting D produces a model of the language of first-order arithmetic.

When D is the full powerset of M, the model is called a full model. The use of full second-order semantics is equivalent to limiting the models of second-order arithmetic to the full models. In fact, the axioms of second-order arithmetic have only one full model. This follows from the fact that the Peano axioms with the second-order induction axiom have only one model under second-order semantics.

Definable functions

[edit]

The first-order functions that are provably total in second-order arithmetic are precisely the same as those representable in system F.[4] Almost equivalently, system F is the theory of functionals corresponding to second-order arithmetic in a manner parallel to how G?del's system T corresponds to first-order arithmetic in the Dialectica interpretation.

More types of models

[edit]

When a model of the language of second-order arithmetic has certain properties, it can also be called these other names:

  • When M is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual operations, is called an ω-model. In this case, the model may be identified with D, its collection of sets of naturals, because this set is enough to completely determine an ω-model. The unique full -model, which is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual structure and all its subsets, is called the intended or standard model of second-order arithmetic.[5]
  • A model of the language of second-order arithmetic is called a β-model if , i.e. the Σ11-statements with parameters from that are satisfied by are the same as those satisfied by the full model.[6] Some notions that are absolute with respect to β-models include " encodes a well-order"[7] and " is a tree".[6]
  • The above result has been extended to the concept of a βn-model for , which has the same definition as the above except is replaced by , i.e. is replaced by .[6] Using this definition β0-models are the same as ω-models.[8]

Subsystems

[edit]

There are many named subsystems of second-order arithmetic.

A subscript 0 in the name of a subsystem indicates that it includes only a restricted portion of the full second-order induction scheme.[9] Such a restriction lowers the proof-theoretic strength of the system significantly. For example, the system ACA0 described below is equiconsistent with Peano arithmetic. The corresponding theory ACA, consisting of ACA0 plus the full second-order induction scheme, is stronger than Peano arithmetic.

Arithmetical comprehension

[edit]

Many of the well-studied subsystems are related to closure properties of models. For example, it can be shown that every ω-model of full second-order arithmetic is closed under Turing jump, but not every ω-model closed under Turing jump is a model of full second-order arithmetic. The subsystem ACA0 includes just enough axioms to capture the notion of closure under Turing jump.

ACA0 is defined as the theory consisting of the basic axioms, the arithmetical comprehension axiom scheme (in other words the comprehension axiom for every arithmetical formula φ) and the ordinary second-order induction axiom. It would be equivalent to also include the entire arithmetical induction axiom scheme, in other words to include the induction axiom for every arithmetical formula φ.

It can be shown that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of ACA0 if and only if S is closed under Turing jump, Turing reducibility, and Turing join.[10]

The subscript 0 in ACA0 indicates that not every instance of the induction axiom scheme is included this subsystem. This makes no difference for ω-models, which automatically satisfy every instance of the induction axiom. It is of importance, however, in the study of non-ω-models. The system consisting of ACA0 plus induction for all formulas is sometimes called ACA with no subscript.

The system ACA0 is a conservative extension of first-order arithmetic (or first-order Peano axioms), defined as the basic axioms, plus the first-order induction axiom scheme (for all formulas φ involving no class variables at all, bound or otherwise), in the language of first-order arithmetic (which does not permit class variables at all). In particular it has the same proof-theoretic ordinal ε0 as first-order arithmetic, owing to the limited induction schema.

The arithmetical hierarchy for formulas

[edit]

A formula is called bounded arithmetical, or Δ00, when all its quantifiers are of the form ?n<t or ?n<t (where n is the individual variable being quantified and t is an individual term), where

stands for

and

stands for

.

A formula is called Σ01 (or sometimes Σ1), respectively Π01 (or sometimes Π1) when it is of the form ?mφ, respectively ?mφ where φ is a bounded arithmetical formula and m is an individual variable (that is free in φ). More generally, a formula is called Σ0n, respectively Π0n when it is obtained by adding existential, respectively universal, individual quantifiers to a Π0n?1, respectively Σ0n?1 formula (and Σ00 and Π00 are both equal to Δ00). By construction, all these formulas are arithmetical (no class variables are ever bound) and, in fact, by putting the formula in Skolem prenex form one can see that every arithmetical formula is logically equivalent to a Σ0n or Π0n formula for all large enough n.

Recursive comprehension

[edit]

The subsystem RCA0 is a weaker system than ACA0 and is often used as the base system in reverse mathematics. It consists of: the basic axioms, the Σ01 induction scheme, and the Δ01 comprehension scheme. The former term is clear: the Σ01 induction scheme is the induction axiom for every Σ01 formula φ. The term "Δ01 comprehension" is more complex, because there is no such thing as a Δ01 formula. The Δ01 comprehension scheme instead asserts the comprehension axiom for every Σ01 formula that is logically equivalent to a Π01 formula. This scheme includes, for every Σ01 formula φ and every Π01 formula ψ, the axiom:

The set of first-order consequences of RCA0 is the same as those of the subsystem IΣ1 of Peano arithmetic in which induction is restricted to Σ01 formulas. In turn, IΣ1 is conservative over primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA) for sentences. Moreover, the proof-theoretic ordinal of is ωω, the same as that of PRA.

It can be seen that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of RCA0 if and only if S is closed under Turing reducibility and Turing join. In particular, the collection of all computable subsets of ω gives an ω-model of RCA0. This is the motivation behind the name of this system—if a set can be proved to exist using RCA0, then the set is recursive (i.e. computable).

Weaker systems

[edit]

Sometimes an even weaker system than RCA0 is desired. One such system is defined as follows: one must first augment the language of arithmetic with an exponential function symbol (in stronger systems the exponential can be defined in terms of addition and multiplication by the usual trick, but when the system becomes too weak this is no longer possible) and the basic axioms by the obvious axioms defining exponentiation inductively from multiplication; then the system consists of the (enriched) basic axioms, plus Δ01 comprehension, plus Δ00 induction.

Stronger systems

[edit]

Over ACA0, each formula of second-order arithmetic is equivalent to a Σ1n or Π1n formula for all large enough n. The system Π11-comprehension is the system consisting of the basic axioms, plus the ordinary second-order induction axiom and the comprehension axiom for every (boldface[11]) Π11 formula φ. This is equivalent to Σ11-comprehension (on the other hand, Δ11-comprehension, defined analogously to Δ01-comprehension, is weaker).

Projective determinacy

[edit]

Projective determinacy is the assertion that every two-player perfect information game with moves being natural numbers, game length ω and projective payoff set is determined, that is, one of the players has a winning strategy. (The first player wins the game if the play belongs to the payoff set; otherwise, the second player wins.) A set is projective if and only if (as a predicate) it is expressible by a formula in the language of second-order arithmetic, allowing real numbers as parameters, so projective determinacy is expressible as a schema in the language of Z2.

Many natural propositions expressible in the language of second-order arithmetic are independent of Z2 and even ZFC but are provable from projective determinacy. Examples include coanalytic perfect subset property, measurability and the property of Baire for sets, uniformization, etc. Over a weak base theory (such as RCA0), projective determinacy implies comprehension and provides an essentially complete theory of second-order arithmetic — natural statements in the language of Z2 that are independent of Z2 with projective determinacy are hard to find.[12]

ZFC + {there are n Woodin cardinals: n is a natural number} is conservative over Z2 with projective determinacy[citation needed], that is a statement in the language of second-order arithmetic is provable in Z2 with projective determinacy if and only if its translation into the language of set theory is provable in ZFC + {there are n Woodin cardinals: n∈N}.

Coding mathematics

[edit]

Second-order arithmetic directly formalizes natural numbers and sets of natural numbers. However, it is able to formalize other mathematical objects indirectly via coding techniques, a fact that was first noticed by Weyl.[13] The integers, rational numbers, and real numbers can all be formalized in the subsystem RCA0, along with complete separable metric spaces and continuous functions between them.[14]

The research program of reverse mathematics uses these formalizations of mathematics in second-order arithmetic to study the set-existence axioms required to prove mathematical theorems.[15] For example, the intermediate value theorem for functions from the reals to the reals is provable in RCA0,[16] while the BolzanoWeierstrass theorem is equivalent to ACA0 over RCA0.[17]

The aforementioned coding works well for continuous and total functions, assuming a higher-order base theory plus weak K?nig's lemma.[18] As perhaps expected, in the case of topology, coding is not without problems.[19]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Hilbert, D.; Bernays, P. (1934). Grundlagen der Mathematik. Springer-Verlag. MR 0237246.
  2. ^ Sieg, W. (2013). Hilbert's Programs and Beyond. Oxford University Press. p. 291. ISBN 978-0-19-970715-7.
  3. ^ a b Shapiro, Stewart (1991). Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. Oxford Logic Guides. Vol. 17. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York. pp. 66, 74–75. ISBN 0-19-853391-8. MR 1143781.
  4. ^ Girard, Jean-Yves (1987). Proofs and Types. Translated by Taylor, Paul. Cambridge University Press. pp. 122–123. ISBN 0-521-37181-3.
  5. ^ Simpson, S. G. (2009). Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic. Perspectives in Logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 3–4. ISBN 978-0-521-88439-6. MR 2517689.
  6. ^ a b c Marek, W. (1974–1975). "Stable sets, a characterization of β2-models of full second order arithmetic and some related facts". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 82: 175–189. doi:10.4064/fm-82-2-175-189. MR 0373897.
  7. ^ Marek, W. (1978). "ω-models of second order arithmetic and admissible sets". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 98 (2): 103–120. doi:10.4064/fm-98-2-103-120. MR 0476490.
  8. ^ Marek, W. (1973). "Observations concerning elementary extensions of ω-models. II". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 38: 227–231. doi:10.2307/2272059. JSTOR 2272059. MR 0337612.
  9. ^ Friedman, H. (1976). "Systems of second order arithmetic with restricted induction, I, II". Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic (Abstracts). 41: 557–559. JSTOR 2272259.
  10. ^ Simpson 2009, pp. 311–313.
  11. ^ Welch, P. D. (2011). "Weak systems of determinacy and arithmetical quasi-inductive definitions" (PDF). The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 76 (2): 418–436. doi:10.2178/jsl/1305810756. MR 2830409.
  12. ^ Woodin, W. H. (2001). "The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 48 (6).
  13. ^ Simpson 2009, p. 16.
  14. ^ Simpson 2009, Chapter II.
  15. ^ Simpson 2009, p. 32.
  16. ^ Simpson 2009, p. 87.
  17. ^ Simpson 2009, p. 34.
  18. ^ Kohlenbach, Ulrich (2002). "Foundational and mathematical uses of higher types". Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics: Essays in honor of Solomon Feferman, Papers from the symposium held at Stanford University, Stanford, CA, December 11–13, 1998. Lecture Notes in Logic. Vol. 15. Urbana, Illinois: Association for Symbolic Logic. pp. 92–116. ISBN 1-56881-169-1. MR 1943304.
  19. ^ Hunter, James (2008). Higher order Reverse Topology (PDF) (Doctoral dissertation). University of Madison-Wisconsin.

Further reading

[edit]
闪点什么意思 中国是什么人种 本科二批是什么意思 mcm中文叫什么牌子 结肠炎有什么症状
卵黄囊回声是什么意思 结缔组织病是什么病 肠胃不舒服挂什么科 内招是什么意思 肾上腺素是什么东西
尿失禁吃什么药 耗儿鱼是什么鱼 阳气不足是什么意思 4月1号什么星座 大张伟的真名叫什么
戊肝是什么病 什么的嗓音 中药什么时候喝 腹部b超挂什么科 o型血为什么叫熊猫血
低血糖和贫血有什么区别hcv9jop4ns7r.cn 尼龙属于什么材料hcv9jop4ns5r.cn 散人是什么意思hcv8jop2ns8r.cn 强心针是什么hcv8jop5ns8r.cn alk是什么意思hcv8jop9ns8r.cn
免冠彩照是什么意思tiangongnft.com 更年期综合征吃什么药hcv7jop6ns4r.cn 肠系膜淋巴结炎吃什么药最有效520myf.com 单车是什么意思hcv8jop9ns1r.cn 这个季节吃什么菜好hcv8jop8ns8r.cn
yrc是什么牌子的鞋hcv9jop0ns9r.cn 一个大一个多念什么hcv9jop2ns7r.cn edv是什么意思hcv9jop1ns1r.cn 前列腺增大是什么原因hcv8jop3ns2r.cn 莲花和荷花有什么区别hcv9jop3ns8r.cn
呔是什么意思hcv8jop1ns3r.cn 白羊座是什么象星座helloaicloud.com 大肝功能是检查什么hcv7jop7ns0r.cn 擦边球是什么意思bjcbxg.com mrt是什么意思hcv9jop2ns6r.cn
百度