宫颈多发潴留囊肿是什么意思| 月子病是什么症状| 邹去掉耳朵旁读什么| 阳虚什么症状| 银行卡销户是什么意思| 跳蚤长什么样子图片| 当今社会什么行业前途比较好| 预防更年期提前应该吃点什么药| 蛇怕什么| 猫癣用什么药| 舌苔厚白腻是什么原因引起的| 钾血症是什么病| 止血敏又叫什么名| 摄影三要素是什么| 八婆是什么意思| 黑死病是什么| 什么是心梗| 三月初什么星座| 鼻涕黄粘稠是什么原因| 木牛流马是什么意思| 小孩子眼睛眨得很频繁是什么原因| 胎儿偏小是什么原因| 尿酸高吃什么药降尿酸效果好| 痉挛是什么意思啊| 50分贝相当于什么声音| 头秃了一块是什么原因| 吃猪血有什么好处和坏处| 肌酐偏低是什么意思| 嘌呤高会引起什么症状| 黄体破裂是什么原因造成的| 老炮儿是什么意思啊| 五道杠是什么牌子| 智商什么意思| 2007年属什么| 腹泻期间宜吃什么食物| 调理是什么意思| 白醋泡脚有什么好处| 什么的原野| 苑字五行属什么| whan是什么意思| 10月12号是什么星座| 挂失补办身份证需要什么| 气泡水是什么水| 类风湿阳性是什么意思| 甘肃天水有什么好玩的地方| 大学毕业是什么学历| 坐是什么结构| cream什么意思| 黄牛用的什么抢票软件| 马蹄是什么| 耐药是什么意思| 头疼恶心吃什么药| fev1是什么意思| wonderland是什么意思| 中午十一点是什么时辰| 鹅蛋炒香菜治什么病| 多多益善什么意思| 海参是补什么的| 为什么会得霉菌感染| 连续做噩梦是什么原因| 夜里咳嗽是什么原因| 母亲节什么时候| 是否是什么意思| 免疫力低会引起什么病| 和珅是什么官| h是什么意思| 利普刀是什么手术| 尿肌酐高是什么原因引起的| 阶段是什么意思| 维c吃多了有什么副作用| 易烊千玺的真名叫什么| 向日葵代表什么生肖| 沉网和浮网有什么区别| 李开复是什么人| 紫癜是一种什么病严重吗| 插入阴道什么感觉| 婴儿蓝是什么颜色| 白眼狼什么意思| 女性检查甲功是什么病| 榕字五行属什么| 恐龙是什么时候灭绝| mri检查是什么| 广州有什么区| 小儿安现在叫什么名| 小野猫是什么意思| 纨绔子弟是什么意思| 尕尕是什么意思| 工匠精神的核心是什么| 膝盖小腿酸软无力是什么原因| 丙氨酸是什么| 忠实是什么意思| 油面筋是什么做的| 杨家将是什么生肖| 吃什么尿酸降得快| 下午三点多是什么时辰| 棋字五行属什么| 草缸适合养什么鱼| 圆明园是什么时候被烧的| 土中金是什么生肖| 恨铁不成钢是什么意思| 另煎兑服是什么意思| 结婚24年是什么婚| 血压低什么原因造成的| 儒字五行属什么| 吃小米粥有什么好处| lhc是什么意思| 大便带血是什么原因| 吃土豆有什么好处| 念珠菌吃什么药最好| 阳春是什么意思| 脚跟疼是什么原因| 跑酷是什么运动| 每天早上起来口苦是什么原因| 君子菜是什么蔬菜| 腰间盘突出睡觉什么姿势好| 检查艾滋病挂什么科| 沦落什么意思| 为什么白头发越来越多| 角质增生是什么意思| 势均力敌是什么意思| 心理学是什么| 小肚子发胀是什么原因女性| 950是什么金| 肚脐眼周围痛什么原因| 儿童说话晚去医院挂什么科| 城隍是什么意思| 同房有点痛什么原因| 猪肉和什么菜搭配最好| 履历是什么意思| 读军校需要什么条件| 整天放屁是什么原因| 耳加贵念什么| 孽缘是什么意思| 喝完酒头疼是什么原因| 丑是什么库| 饿了么什么时候成立的| 梁伟文 为什么叫林夕| 乌龟代表什么生肖| 翼字五行属什么| 酱是什么意思| 一级军士长是什么级别| 夜盲症是什么| 黄瓜是绿色的为什么叫黄瓜| 籽字五行属什么| 什么是乳头瘤| 鸡尖是什么| 骨质疏松是什么原因引起的| 榴莲和什么相克| 血液为什么是红色的| 九月十五日是什么星座| 游坦之练的什么武功| bata鞋属于什么档次| 心绪不宁的意思是什么| cha什么意思| mcn是什么意思| 公立医院和私立医院有什么区别| 11月30号是什么星座| 这个是什么表情| 婴儿吃dha有什么好处| 什么的叮咛| 拿铁咖啡什么意思| 点石成金是什么意思| 桦树茸的功效主治什么病| 血脂高吃什么降血脂| dwi呈高信号什么意思| 咖啡色是什么颜色| 锦鲤跳缸是什么原因| 芦笋是什么植物| 鹅蛋脸适合什么刘海| 胃肠化是什么意思| 唐筛和无创有什么区别| 山今读什么| 左侧头疼是什么原因引起的| 一毛不拔是什么生肖| 兄弟是什么生肖| 烧心吃什么食物好得快| 大便拉不干净是什么原因| 白粉病用什么药| 四大才子是什么生肖| 茶叶水洗脸有什么好处| 更年期失眠吃什么药效果好| 耍无赖是什么意思| 来日方长是什么意思| 什么是eb病毒| 傀儡什么意思| 梦见牛粪是什么意思| 白脉病西医叫什么病| 滥情什么意思| 做梦买鞋是什么意思| 阿玛施属于什么档次| 夏天的诗句有什么| 吃完泡面吃什么解毒| 痔疮出血用什么药| 马跟什么生肖最配| cl是什么牌子| 居心叵测是什么意思| 梦见大便是什么意思| pbc是什么| 瘢痕子宫什么意思| qh是什么意思| 窥视是什么意思| 三十七岁属什么生肖| 录取通知书是什么生肖| 低筋面粉可以做什么| 副主任科员是什么级别| 零四年属什么| 拉谷谷女装什么档次的| notebook什么意思| 什么关系| 吃什么补脑子增强记忆力最快| 无情是什么意思| 子宫腺肌症有什么症状| 美国为什么有哥伦比亚| 2006年出生的是什么命| 心里发慌什么原因| 牙痛吃什么药效果最好| 轻度肠上皮化生是什么意思| 做梦梦到对象出轨是什么意思| 未见胎芽是什么意思| 妥协是什么意思| 手指没有月牙是什么原因| 肠胃炎拉肚子吃什么药| 男人不长胡子是什么原因| 腿膝盖后面的窝窝疼是什么原因| 一龙一什么填十二生肖| 孤单的反义词是什么| 午时属什么生肖| 胃疼做什么检查| 印度为什么没把墨脱占领| 甚微是什么意思| 脑控是什么| ft是什么单位| 地铁站务员是干什么的| 早搏有什么危害| 落井下石是什么意思| 皮肤经常痒是什么原因| 泌尿系统感染有什么症状| 低血糖和贫血有什么区别| 百花齐放是什么生肖| 通宵是什么意思| 为什么现在| 颈动脉强回声斑块是什么意思| 舌头发紫是什么原因| 远视储备是什么意思| 青榄配什么煲汤止咳做法| 立秋日有什么禁忌| 上户口需要什么资料| 女人要的是什么| tvoc是什么| 月经不调吃什么调理| 百香果什么时候吃最好| 蜜蜂吃什么食物| 什么叫自私的人| 拉肚子应该吃什么| 肝火旺盛是什么原因引起的| 气胸是什么病是大病吗| 小孩牙疼吃什么药| 断念是什么意思| 晚上2点是什么时辰| ems是什么意思| 咽炎是什么原因引起的| 梦到火是什么意思| 代言人是什么意思| 双儿是什么意思| 百度Jump to content

长达专业报告 AI被黑客滥用的风险与日俱增

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 该公司是一家拥有60亿美金资产的全球性工业企业,从事工业气体、电子原料、医疗服务和表面处理。

Tarski's axioms are an axiom system for Euclidean geometry, specifically for that portion of Euclidean geometry that is formulable in first-order logic with identity (i.e. is formulable as an elementary theory). As such, it does not require an underlying set theory. The only primitive objects of the system are "points" and the only primitive predicates are "betweenness" (expressing the fact that a point lies on a line segment between two other points) and "congruence" (expressing the fact that the distance between two points equals the distance between two other points). The system contains infinitely many axioms.

The axiom system is due to Alfred Tarski who first presented it in 1926.[1] Other modern axiomizations of Euclidean geometry are Hilbert's axioms (1899) and Birkhoff's axioms (1932).

Using his axiom system, Tarski was able to show that the first-order theory of Euclidean geometry is consistent, complete and decidable: every sentence in its language is either provable or disprovable from the axioms, and we have an algorithm which decides for any given sentence whether it is provable or not.

Overview

[edit]

Early in his career Tarski taught geometry and researched set theory. His coworker Steven Givant (1999) explained Tarski's take-off point:

From Enriques, Tarski learned of the work of Mario Pieri, an Italian geometer who was strongly influenced by Peano. Tarski preferred Pieri's system [of his Point and Sphere memoir], where the logical structure and the complexity of the axioms were more transparent.

Givant then says that "with typical thoroughness" Tarski devised his system:

What was different about Tarski's approach to geometry? First of all, the axiom system was much simpler than any of the axiom systems that existed up to that time. In fact the length of all of Tarski's axioms together is not much more than just one of Pieri's 24 axioms. It was the first system of Euclidean geometry that was simple enough for all axioms to be expressed in terms of the primitive notions only, without the help of defined notions. Of even greater importance, for the first time a clear distinction was made between full geometry and its elementary — that is, its first order — part.

Like other modern axiomatizations of Euclidean geometry, Tarski's employs a formal system consisting of symbol strings, called sentences, whose construction respects formal syntactical rules, and rules of proof that determine the allowed manipulations of the sentences. Unlike some other modern axiomatizations, such as Birkhoff's and Hilbert's, Tarski's axiomatization has no primitive objects other than points, so a variable or constant cannot refer to a line or an angle. Because points are the only primitive objects, and because Tarski's system is a first-order theory, it is not even possible to define lines as sets of points. The only primitive relations (predicates) are "betweenness" and "congruence" among points.

Tarski's axiomatization is shorter than its rivals, in a sense Tarski and Givant (1999) make explicit. It is more concise than Pieri's because Pieri had only two primitive notions while Tarski introduced three: point, betweenness, and congruence. Such economy of primitive and defined notions means that Tarski's system is not very convenient for doing Euclidean geometry. Rather, Tarski designed his system to facilitate its analysis via the tools of mathematical logic, i.e., to facilitate deriving its metamathematical properties. Tarski's system has the unusual property that all sentences can be written in universal-existential form, a special case of the prenex normal form. This form has all universal quantifiers preceding any existential quantifiers, so that all sentences can be recast in the form This fact allowed Tarski to prove that Euclidean geometry is decidable: there exists an algorithm which can determine the truth or falsity of any sentence. Tarski's axiomatization is also complete. This does not contradict G?del's first incompleteness theorem, because Tarski's theory lacks the expressive power needed to interpret Robinson arithmetic (Franzén 2005, pp. 25–26).

The axioms

[edit]

Alfred Tarski worked on the axiomatization and metamathematics of Euclidean geometry intermittently from 1926 until his death in 1983, with Tarski (1959) heralding his mature interest in the subject. The work of Tarski and his students on Euclidean geometry culminated in the monograph Schwabh?user, Szmielew, and Tarski (1983), which set out the 10 axioms and one axiom schema shown below, the associated metamathematics, and a fair bit of the subject. Gupta (1965) made important contributions, and Tarski and Givant (1999) discuss the history.

Fundamental relations

[edit]

These axioms are a more elegant version of a set Tarski devised in the 1920s as part of his investigation of the metamathematical properties of Euclidean plane geometry. This objective required reformulating that geometry as a first-order theory. Tarski did so by positing a universe of points, with lower case letters denoting variables ranging over that universe. Equality is provided by the underlying logic (see First-order logic#Equality and its axioms).[2] Tarski then posited two primitive relations:

  • Betweenness, a triadic relation. The atomic sentence Bxyz denotes that the point y is "between" the points x and z, in other words, that y is a point on the line segment xz. (This relation is interpreted inclusively, so that Bxyz is trivially true whenever x=y or y=z).
  • Congruence (or "equidistance"), a tetradic relation. The atomic sentence Cwxyz or commonly wxyz can be interpreted as wx is congruent to yz, in other words, that the length of the line segment wx is equal to the length of the line segment yz.

Betweenness captures the affine aspect (such as the parallelism of lines) of Euclidean geometry; congruence, its metric aspect (such as angles and distances). The background logic includes identity, a binary relation denoted by =.

The axioms below are grouped by the types of relation they invoke, then sorted, first by the number of existential quantifiers, then by the number of atomic sentences. The axioms should be read as universal closures; hence any free variables should be taken as tacitly universally quantified.

Congruence axioms

[edit]
Reflexivity of congruence
Identity of congruence
Transitivity of congruence

Commentary

[edit]

While the congruence relation is, formally, a 4-way relation among points, it may also be thought of, informally, as a binary relation between two line segments and . The reflexivity and transitivity axioms above, combined, prove both:

  • that this binary relation is in fact an equivalence relation
    • it is reflexive: .
    • it is symmetric .
    • it is transitive .
  • and that the order in which the points of a line segment are specified is irrelevant.
    • .
    • .
    • .

The transitivity axiom asserts that congruence is Euclidean, in that it respects the first of Euclid's "common notions".

The identity of congruence axiom states, intuitively, that if xy is congruent with a segment that begins and ends at the same point, x and y are the same point. This is closely related to the notion of reflexivity for binary relations.

Betweenness axioms

[edit]
Pasch's axiom
Identity of betweenness

The only point on the line segment is itself.

Axiom of Pasch
Continuity: φ and ψ divide the ray into two halves and the axiom asserts the existence of a point b dividing those two halves
Axiom schema of continuity

Let φ(x) and ψ(y) be first-order formulae containing no free instances of either a or b. Let there also be no free instances of x in ψ(y) or of y in φ(x). Then all instances of the following schema are axioms:

Let r be a ray with endpoint a. Let the first order formulae φ and ψ define subsets X and Y of r, such that every point in Y is to the right of every point of X (with respect to a). Then there exists a point b in r lying between X and Y. This is essentially the Dedekind cut construction, carried out in a way that avoids quantification over sets.

Note that the formulae φ(x) and ψ(y) may contain parameters, i.e. free variables different from a, b, x, y. And indeed, each instance of the axiom scheme that does not contain parameters can be proven from the other axioms.[3]

Lower dimension

There exist three noncollinear points. Without this axiom, the theory could be modeled by the one-dimensional real line, a single point, or even the empty set.

Congruence and betweenness

[edit]
Upper dimension axiom
Upper dimension

Three points equidistant from two distinct points form a line. Without this axiom, the theory could be modeled by three-dimensional or higher-dimensional space.

Axiom of Euclid

Three variants of this axiom can be given, labeled A, B and C below. They are equivalent to each other given the remaining Tarski's axioms, and indeed equivalent to Euclid's parallel postulate.

A:

Let a line segment join the midpoint of two sides of a given triangle. That line segment will be half as long as the third side. This is equivalent to the interior angles of any triangle summing to two right angles.

B:

Given any triangle, there exists a circle that includes all of its vertices.

Axiom of Euclid: C
C:

Given any angle and any point v in its interior, there exists a line segment including v, with an endpoint on each side of the angle.

Each variant has an advantage over the others:

  • A dispenses with existential quantifiers;
  • B has the fewest variables and atomic sentences;
  • C requires but one primitive notion, betweenness. This variant is the usual one given in the literature.
Five segment
Five segment

Begin with two triangles, xuz and x'u'z'. Draw the line segments yu and y'u', connecting a vertex of each triangle to a point on the side opposite to the vertex. The result is two divided triangles, each made up of five segments. If four segments of one triangle are each congruent to a segment in the other triangle, then the fifth segments in both triangles must be congruent.

This is equivalent to the side-angle-side rule for determining that two triangles are congruent; if the angles uxz and u'x'z' are congruent (there exist congruent triangles xuz and x'u'z'), and the two pairs of incident sides are congruent (xu ≡ x'u' and xz ≡ x'z'), then the remaining pair of sides is also congruent (uz ≡ u'z').

Segment construction

For any point y, it is possible to draw in any direction (determined by x) a line congruent to any segment ab.

Discussion

[edit]

According to Tarski and Givant (1999: 192-93), none of the above axioms are fundamentally new. The first four axioms establish some elementary properties of the two primitive relations. For instance, reflexivity and transitivity of congruence establish that congruence is an equivalence relation over line segments. The identity of congruence and of betweenness govern the trivial case when those relations are applied to nondistinct points. The theorem xyzz ? x=y ? Bxyx extends these Identity axioms.

A number of other properties of betweenness are derivable as theorems[4] including:

The last two properties totally order the points making up a line segment.

The upper and lower dimension axioms together require that any model of these axioms have dimension 2, i.e. that we are axiomatizing the Euclidean plane. Suitable changes in these axioms yield axiom sets for Euclidean geometry for dimensions 0, 1, and greater than 2 (Tarski and Givant 1999: Axioms 8(1), 8(n), 9(0), 9(1), 9(n) ). Note that solid geometry requires no new axioms, unlike the case with Hilbert's axioms. Moreover, lower dimension for n dimensions is simply the negation of upper dimension for n - 1 dimensions.

When the number of dimensions is greater than 1, betweenness can be defined in terms of congruence (Tarski and Givant, 1999). First define the relation "≤" (where is interpreted "the length of line segment is less than or equal to the length of line segment "):

In the case of two dimensions, the intuition is as follows: For any line segment xy, consider the possible range of lengths of xv, where v is any point on the perpendicular bisector of xy. It is apparent that while there is no upper bound to the length of xv, there is a lower bound, which occurs when v is the midpoint of xy. So if xy is shorter than or equal to zu, then the range of possible lengths of xv will be a superset of the range of possible lengths of zw, where w is any point on the perpendicular bisector of zu.

Betweenness can then be defined by using the intuition that the shortest distance between any two points is a straight line:

The axiom schema of continuity assures that the ordering of points on a line is complete (with respect to first-order definable properties). As was pointed out by Tarski, this first-order axiom schema may be replaced by a more powerful second-order axiom of continuity if one allows for variables to refer to arbitrary sets of points. The resulting second-order system is equivalent to Hilbert's set of axioms. (Tarski and Givant 1999)

The axioms of Pasch and Euclid are well known. The segment construction axiom makes measurement and the Cartesian coordinate system possible—simply assign the length 1 to some arbitrary non-empty line segment. Indeed, it is shown in (Schwabh?user 1983) that by specifying two distinguished points on a line, called 0 and 1, we can define an addition, multiplication and ordering, turning the set of points on that line into a real-closed ordered field. We can then introduce coordinates from this field, showing that every model of Tarski's axioms is isomorphic to the two-dimensional plane over some real-closed ordered field.

The standard geometric notions of parallelism and intersection of lines (where lines are represented by two distinct points on them), right angles, congruence of angles, similarity of triangles, tangency of lines and circles (represented by a center point and a radius) can all be defined in Tarski's system.

Let wff stand for a well-formed formula (or syntactically correct first-order formula) in Tarski's system. Tarski and Givant (1999: 175) proved that Tarski's system is:

This has the consequence that every statement of (second-order, general) Euclidean geometry which can be formulated as a first-order sentence in Tarski's system is true if and only if it is provable in Tarski's system, and this provability can be automatically checked with Tarski's algorithm. This, for instance, applies to all theorems in Euclid's Elements, Book I. An example of a theorem of Euclidean geometry which cannot be so formulated is the Archimedean property: to any two positive-length line segments S1 and S2 there exists a natural number n such that nS1 is longer than S2. (This is a consequence of the fact that there are real-closed fields that contain infinitesimals.[5]) Other notions that cannot be expressed in Tarski's system are the constructability with straightedge and compass and statements that talk about "all polygones" etc.[6]

Gupta (1965) proved the Tarski's axioms independent, excepting Pasch and reflexivity of congruence.

Negating the axiom of Euclid yields hyperbolic geometry, while eliminating it outright yields absolute geometry. Full (as opposed to elementary) Euclidean geometry requires giving up a first order axiomatization: replace φ(x) and ψ(y) in the axiom schema of Continuity with xA and yB, where A and B are universally quantified variables ranging over sets of points.

Further simplifications for the fragment describing the plane Euclidean geometry of ruler and segment-transporter constructions, as well as for that of ruler and compass constructions were provided in (Pambuccian 2024). Each axiom of the axiom systems presented there is a prenex statement with at most 5 variables.

Comparison with Hilbert's system

[edit]

Hilbert's axioms for plane geometry number 16, and include transitivity of congruence and a variant of the axiom of Pasch. The only notion from intuitive geometry invoked in the remarks to Tarski's axioms is triangle. (Versions B and C of the axiom of Euclid refer to "circle" and "angle," respectively.) Hilbert's axioms also require "ray," "angle," and the notion of a triangle "including" an angle. In addition to betweenness and congruence, Hilbert's axioms require a primitive binary relation "on," linking a point and a line.

Hilbert uses two axioms of continuity, and they require second-order logic. By contrast, Tarski's axiom schema of continuity consists of infinitely many first-order axioms. Such a schema is indispensable; Euclidean geometry in Tarski's (or equivalent) language cannot be finitely axiomatized as a first-order theory.

Hilbert's system is therefore considerably stronger: every model is isomorphic to the real plane (using the standard notions of points and lines). By contrast, Tarski's system has many non-isomorphic models: for every real-closed field F, the plane F2 provides one such model (where betweenness and congruence are defined in the obvious way).[7]

The first four groups of axioms of Hilbert's axioms for plane geometry are bi-interpretable with Tarski's axioms minus continuity.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Tarski 1959, Tarski and Givant 1999
  2. ^ Tarski & Givant 1999, p. 177.
  3. ^ Schwabh?user 1983, p. 287-288
  4. ^ Tarski and Givant 1999, p. 189
  5. ^ Greenberg 2010
  6. ^ McNaughton, Robert (1953). "Review: A decision method for elementary algebra and geometry by A. Tarski" (PDF). Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 59 (1): 91–93. doi:10.1090/s0002-9904-1953-09664-1.
  7. ^ Schwabh?user 1983, section I.16

References

[edit]


人体最大器官是什么 bmr是什么意思 卵巢保养最好的方法是什么 葬花是什么意思 悦五行属性是什么
纷至沓来是什么意思 祸害是什么意思 鹦鹉能吃什么水果 海鲜中毒有什么反应 牙龈翻瓣术是什么意思
正月十九是什么日子 脑出血什么原因引起的 什么水果是降火的 双手麻木是什么原因 梦见老虎是什么预兆
母亲吃什么退婴儿黄疸 矬子是什么意思 兆后面的单位是什么 怀孕了胃不舒服是什么原因 最小的一位数是什么
鸡汤炖什么菜好吃hcv8jop3ns0r.cn 梦见饺子是什么意思hcv8jop1ns7r.cn 感冒冒虚汗是什么原因naasee.com 68岁属什么生肖hcv8jop8ns0r.cn 被舔下面是什么感觉hcv8jop2ns6r.cn
核磁共振是查什么的hkuteam.com 图什么96micro.com 鹿晗的原名叫什么sscsqa.com 血糖高吃什么水果好能降糖0735v.com 食色性也是什么意思hcv8jop4ns9r.cn
孕妇为什么那么怕热hcv9jop0ns2r.cn 参谋长是什么军衔hcv9jop1ns1r.cn 那敢情好是什么意思hcv7jop5ns5r.cn 孔雀翎是什么东西hcv9jop1ns2r.cn 胸膈痞闷是什么症状hcv8jop3ns2r.cn
总胆固醇偏低是什么意思hcv8jop9ns9r.cn 九月二十三是什么星座hcv9jop7ns0r.cn 指教是什么意思hcv9jop4ns0r.cn 身上冷是什么原因hcv8jop9ns3r.cn 苦荞茶有什么功效hcv8jop8ns5r.cn
百度